Chapter 12
THE STATE OF LONG-TERM EXPECTATION
I
We have seen in the previous chapter that the scale of
investment depends on the relation between the rate of interest
and the schedule of the marginal efficiency of capital
corresponding to different scales of current investment, whilst
the marginal efficiency of capital depends on the relation
between the supply price of a capital-asset and its prospective
yield. In this chapter we shall consider in more detail some of
the factors which determine the prospective yield of an asset.
The considerations upon which expectations of prospective
yields are based are partly existing facts which we can assume to
be known more or less for certain, and partly future events which
can only be forecasted with more or less confidence. Amongst the
first may be mentioned the existing stock of various types of
capital-assets and of capital-assets in general and the strength
of the existing consumers' demand for goods which require for
their efficient production a relatively larger assistance from
capital. Amongst the latter are future changes in the type and
quantity of the stock of capital-assets and in the tastes of the
consumer, the strength of effective demand from time to time
during the life of the investment under consideration, and the
changes in the wage-unit in terms of money which may occur during
its life. We may sum up the state of psychological expectation
which covers the latter as being the state of long-term expectation;セas distinguished from the short-term
expectation upon the basis of which a producer estimates what he
will get for a product when it is finished if he decides to begin
producing it to-day with the existing plant, which we examined in
chapter 5.
II
It would be foolish, in forming our expectations, to attach
great weight to matters which are very uncertain.
It is reasonable, therefore, to be guided to a considerable
degree by the facts about which we feel somewhat confident, even
though they may be less decisively relevant to the issue than
other facts about which our knowledge is vague and scanty. For
this reason the facts of the existing situation enter, in a sense
disproportionately, into the formation of our long-term
expectations; our usual practice being to take the existing
situation and to project it into the future, modified only to the
extent that we have more or less definite reasons for expecting a
change.
The state of long-term expectation, upon which our decisions
are based, does not solely depend, therefore, on the most
probable forecast we can make. It also depends on the confidence
with which we make this forecastセon
how highly we rate the likelihood of our best forecast turning
out quite wrong. If we expect large changes but are very
uncertain as to what precise form these changes will take, then
our confidence will be weak.
The state of confidence, as they term it, is a matter
to which practical men always pay the closest and most anxious
attention. But economists have not analysed it carefully and have
been content, as a rule, to discuss it in general terms. In particular it has not been made clear
that its relevance to economic problems comes in through its
important influence on the schedule of the marginal efficiency of
capital. There are not two separate factors affecting the rate of
investment, namely, the schedule of the marginal efficiency of
capital and the state of confidence. The state of confidence is
relevant because it is one of the major factors determining the
former, which is the same thing as the investment
demand-schedule.
There is, however, not much to be said about the state of
confidence a priori. Our conclusions must mainly depend
upon the actual observation of markets and business psychology.
This is the reason why the ensuing digression is on a different
level of abstraction from most of this book.
For convenience of exposition we shall assume in the following
discussion of the state of confidence that there are no changes
in the rate of interest; and we shall write, throughout the
following sections, as if changes in the values of investments
were solely due to changes in the expectation of their
prospective yields and not at all to changes in the rate of
interest at which these prospective yields are capitalised. The
effect of changes in the rate of interest is, however, easily
superimposed on the effect of changes in the state of confidence.
III
The outstanding fact is the extreme precariousness of the
basis of knowledge on which our estimates of prospective yield
have to be made. Our knowledge of the factors which will govern
the yield of an investment some years hence is usually very
slight and often negligible. If we speak frankly, we have to
admit that our basis of knowledge for estimating the yield ten
years hence of a railway, a copper mine, a textile factory, the
goodwill of a patent medicine, an Atlantic liner, a building in the City of London amounts to little and
sometimes to nothing; or even five years hence. In fact, those
who seriously attempt to make any such estimate are often so much
in the minority that their behaviour does not govern the market.
In former times, when enterprises were mainly owned by those
who undertook them or by their friends and associates, investment
depended on a sufficient supply of individuals of sanguine
temperament and constructive impulses who embarked on business as
a way of life, not really relying on a precise calculation of
prospective profit. The affair was partly a lottery, though with
the ultimate result largely governed by whether the abilities and
character of the managers were above or below the average. Some
would fail and some would succeed. But even after the event no
one would know whether the average results in terms of the sums
invested had exceeded, equalled or fallen short of the prevailing
rate of interest; though, if we exclude the exploitation of
natural resources and monopolies, it is probable that the actual
average results of investments, even during periods of progress
and prosperity, have disappointed the hopes which prompted them.
Business men play a mixed game of skill and chance, the average
results of which to the players are not known by those who take a
hand. If human nature felt no temptation to take a chance, no
satisfaction (profit apart) in constructing a factory, a railway,
a mine or a farm, there might not be much investment merely as a
result of cold calculation.
Decisions to invest in private business of the old-fashioned
type were, however, decisions largely irrevocable, not only for
the community as a whole, but also for the individual. With the
separation between ownership and management which prevails to-day
and with the development of organised investment markets, a new
factor of great importance has entered in, which sometimes
facilitates investment but sometimes adds greatly to the instability of the system. In the absence of
security markets, there is no object in frequently attempting to
revalue an investment to which we are committed. But the Stock
Exchange revalues many investments every day and the revaluations
give a frequent opportunity to the individual (though not to the
community as a whole) to revise his commitments. It is as though
a farmer, having tapped his barometer after breakfast, could
decide to remove his capital from the farming business between 10
and II in the morning and reconsider whether he should return to
it later in the week. But the daily revaluations of the Stock
Exchange, though they are primarily made to facilitate transfers
of old investments between one individual and another, inevitably
exert a decisive influence on the rate of current investment. For
there is no sense in building up a new enterprise at a cost
greater than that at which a similar existing enterprise can be
purchased; whilst there is an inducement to spend on a new
project what may seem an extravagant sum, if it can be floated
off on the Stock Exchange at an immediate profit.
Thus certain classes of investment are governed by the average
expectation of those who deal on the Stock Exchange as revealed
in the price of shares, rather than by the genuine expectations
of the professional entrepreneur.
How then are these highly significant daily, even hourly,
revaluations of existing investments carried out in practice?
In practice we have tacitly agreed, as a rule, to fall back on
what is, in truth, a convention. The essence of this
conventionセthough it does not, of
course, work out quite so simplyセlies
in assuming that the existing state of affairs will continue
indefinitely, except in so far as we have specific reasons to
expect a change. This does not mean that we really believe that
the existing state of affairs will continue indefinitely. We know
from extensive experience that this is most unlikely. The actual
results of an investment over a long term of years very seldom
agree with the initial expectation. Nor can we rationalise our
behaviour by arguing that to a man in a state of ignorance errors
in either direction are equally probable, so that there remains a
mean actuarial expectation based on equi-probabilities. For it
can easily be shown that the assumption of arithmetically equal
probabilities based on a state of ignorance leads to absurdities.
We are assuming, in effect, that the existing market valuation,
however arrived at, is uniquely correct in relation to our
existing knowledge of the facts which will influence the yield of
the investment, and that it will only change in proportion to
changes in this knowledge; though, philosophically speaking, it
cannot be uniquely correct, since our existing knowledge does not
provide a sufficient basis for a calculated mathematical
expectation. In point of fact, all sorts of considerations enter
into the market valuation which are in no way relevant to the
prospective yield.
Nevertheless the above conventional method of calculation will
be compatible with a considerable measure of continuity and
stability in our affairs, so long as we can rely on the
maintenance of the convention.
For if there exist organised investment markets and if we can
rely on the maintenance of the convention, an investor can
legitimately encourage himself with the idea that the only risk he runs is that of a genuine change in
the news over the near future, as to the likelihood of
which he can attempt to form his own judgment, and which is
unlikely to be very large. For, assuming that the convention
holds good, it is only these changes which can affect the value
of his investment, and he need not lose hiS sleep merely because
he has not any notion what his investment will be worth ten years
hence. Thus investment becomes reasonably 'safe' for the
individual investor over short periods, and hence over a
succession of short periods however many, if he can fairly rely
on there being no breakdown in the convention and on his
therefore having an opportunity to revise his judgment and change
his investment, before there has been time for much to happen.
Investments which are 'fixed' for the community are thus made
'liquid' for the individual.
It has been, I am sure, on the basis of some such procedure as
this that our leading investment markets have been developed. But
it is not surprising that a convention, in an absolute view of
things so arbitrary, should have its weak points. It is its
precariousness which creates no small part of our contemporary
problem of securing sufficient investment.
V
Some of the factors which accentuate this precariousness may
be briefly mentioned.
(1) As a result of the gradual increase in the
proportion of the equity in the community's aggregate capital
investment which is owned by persons who do not manage and have
no special knowledge of the circumstances, either actual or
prospective, of the business in question, the element of real
knowledge in the valuation of investments by whose who own them
or contemplate purchasing them has seriously declined.
(2) Day-to-day fluctuations in the profits of
existing investments, which are obviously of an ephemeral and
non-significant character, tend to have an altogether excessive,
and even an absurd, influence on the market. It is said, for
example, that the shares of American companies which manufacture
ice tend to sell at a higher price in summer when their profits
are seasonally high than in winter when no one wants ice. The
recurrence of a bank-holiday may raise the market valuation of
the British railway system by several million pounds.
(3) A conventional valuation which is established
as the outcome of the mass psychology of a large number of
ignorant individuals is liable to change violently as the result
ofa sudden fluctuation of opinion due to factors which do not
really make much difference to the prospective yield; since there
will be no strong roots of conviction to hold it steady. In
abnormal times in particular, when the hypothesis of an
indefinite continuance of the existing state of affairs is less
plausible than usual even though there are no express grounds to
anticipate a definite change, the market will be subject to waves
of optimistic and pessimistic sentiment, which are unreasoning
and yet in a sense legitimate where no solid basis exists for a
reasonable calculation.
(4) But there is one feature in particular which
deserves our attention. It might have been supposed that
competition between expert professionals, possessing judgment and
knowledge beyond that of the average private investor, would
correct the vagaries of the ignorant individual left to himself.
It happens, however, that the energies and skill of the
professional investor and speculator are mainly occupied
otherwise. For most of these persons are, in fact, largely
concerned, not with making superior long-term forecasts of the
probable yield of an investment over its whole life, but with
foreseeing changes in the conventional basis of valuation a short
time ahead of the general public. They are concerned, not with
what an investment is really worth to a man who buys it 'for keeps', but with what
the market will value it at, under the influence of mass
psychology, three months or a year hence. Moreover, this
behaviour is not the outcome of a wrong-headed propensity. It is
an inevitable result of an investment market organised along the
lines described. For it is not sensible to pay 25 for an
investment of which you believe the prospective yield to justify
a value of 30, if you also believe that the market will value it
at 20 three months hence.
Thus the professional investor is forced to concern himself
with the anticipation of impending changes, in the news or in the
atmosphere, of the kind by which experience shows that the mass
psychology of the market is most influenced. This is the
inevitable result of investment markets organised with a view to
so-called 'liquidity'. Of the maxims of orthodox finance none,
surely, is more anti-social than the fetish of liquidity, the
doctrine that it is a positive virtue on the part of investment
institutions to concentrate their resources upon the holding of
'liquid' securities. It forgets that there is no such thing as
liquidity of investment for the community as a whole. The social
object of skilled investment should be to defeat the dark forces
of time and ignorance which envelop our future. The actual,
private object of the most skilled investment to-day is 'to beat
the gun', as the Americans so well express it, to outwit the
crowd, and to pass the bad, or depreciating, half-crown to the
other fellow.
This battle of wits to anticipate the basis of conventional
valuation a few months hence, rather than the prospective yield
of an investment over a long term of years, does not even require
gulls amongst the public to feed the maws of the professional;セit can be played by professionals amongst
themselves. Nor is it necessary that anyone should keep his
simple faith in the conventional basis of valuation having any
genuine long-term validity. For it is, so to speak, a game of
Snap, of Old Maid, of Musical Chairsセa
pastime in which he is victor who says Snap neither too
soon nor too late, who passed the Old Maid to his neighbour
before the game is over, who secures a chair for himself when the
music stops. These games can be played with zest and enjoyment,
though all the players know that it is the Old Maid which is
circulating, or that when the music stops some of the players
will find themselves unseated.
Or, to change the metaphor slightly, professional investment
may be likened to those newspaper competitions in which the
competitors have to pick out the six prettiest faces from a
hundred photographs, the prize being awarded to the competitor
whose choice most nearly corresponds to the average preferences
of the competitors as a whole; so that each competitor has to
pick, not those faces which he himself finds prettiest, but those
which he thinks likeliest to catch the fancy of the other
competitors, all of whom are looking at the problem from the same
point of view. It is not a case of choosing those which, to the
best of one's judgment, are really the prettiest, nor even those
which average opinion genuinely thinks the prettiest. We have
reached the third degree where we devote our intelligences to
anticipating what average opinion expects the average opinion to
be. And there are some, I believe, who practise the fourth, fifth
and higher degrees.
If the reader interjects that there must surely be large
profits to be gained from the other players in the long run by a
skilled individual who, unperturbed by the prevailing pastime,
continues to purchase investments on the best genuine long-term
expectations he can frame, he must be answered, first of all,
that there are, indeed, such serious-minded individuals and that
it makes a vast difference to an investment market whether or not
they predominate in their influence over the game-players. But we
must also add that there are several factors which jeopardise the predominance of such
individuals in modern investment markets. Investment based on
genuine long-term expectation is so difficult to-day as to be
scarcely practicable. He who attempts it must surely lead much
more laborious days and run greater risks than he who tries to
guess better than the crowd how thc crowd will behave; and, given
equal intelligence, he may make more disastrous mistakes. There
is no clear evidence from experience that the investment policy
which is socially advantageous coincides with that which is most
profitable. It needs more intelligence to defeat the forces of
time and our ignorance of the future than to beat the gun.
Moreover, life is not long enough;セhuman
nature desires quick results, there is a peculiar zest in making
money quickly, and remoter gains are discounted by the average
man at a very high rate. The game of professional investment is
intolerably boring and over-exacting to anyone who is entirely
exempt from the gambling instinct; whilst he who has it must pay
to this propensity the appropriate toll. Furthermore, an investor
who proposes to ignore near-term market fluctuations needs
greater resources for safety and must not operate on so large a
scale, if at all, with borrowed moneyセa
further reason for the higher return from the pastime to a given
stock of intelligence and resources. Finally it is the long-term
investor, he who most promotes the public interest, who will in
practice come in for most criticism, wherever investment funds
are managed by committees or boards or banks.
For it is in the essence of his behaviour that he should be
eccentric, unconventional and rash in the eyes of average
opinion. If he is successful, that will only confirm the general
belief in his rashness; and if in the short run he is unsuccessful, which is very likely, he
will not receive much mercy. Worldly wisdom teaches that it is
better for reputation to fail conventionally than to succeed
unconventionally.
(5) So far we have had chiefly in mind the state of confidence
of the speculator or speculative investor himself and may have
seemed to be tacitly assuming that, if he himself is satisfied
with the prospects, he has unlimited command over money at the
market rate of interest. This is, of course, not the case. Thus
we must also take account of the other facet of the state of
confidence, namely, the confidence of the lending institutions
towards those who seek to borrow from them, sometimes described
as the state of credit. A collapse in the price of equities,
which has had disastrous reactions on the marginal efficiency of
capital, may have been due to the weakening either of speculative
confidence or of the state of credit. But whereas the weakening
of either is enough to cause a collapse, recovery requires the
revival of both. For whilst the weakening of credit is
sufficient to bring about a collapse, its strengthening, though a
necessary condition of recovery, is not a sufficient condition.
VI
These considerations should not lie beyond the purview of the
economist. But they must be relegated to their right perspective.
If I may be allowed to appropriate the term speculation for
the activity of forecasting the psychology of the market, and the
term enterprise for the activity of forecasting the
prospective yield of assets over their whole life, it is by no
means always the case that speculation predominates over
enterprise. As the organisation of investment markets improves,
the risk of the predominance of speculation does, however,
increase. In one of the greatest investment markets in the world,
namely, New York, the influence of speculation (in the above sense) is enormous.
Even outside the field of finance, Americans are apt to be unduly
interested in discovering what average opinion believes average
opinion to be; and this national weakness finds its nemesis in
the stock market. It is rare, one is told, for an American to
invest, as many Englishmen still do, 'for income'; and he will
not readily purchase an investment except in the hope of capital
appreciation. This is only another way of saying that, when he
purchases an investment, the American is attaching his hopes, not
so much to its prospective yield, as to a favourable change in
the conventional basis of valuation, i.e. that he is, in the
above sense, a speculator. Speculators may do no harm as bubbles
on a steady stream of enterprise. But the position is serious
when enterprise becomes the bubble on a whirlpool of speculation.
When the capital development of a country becomes a by-product of
the activities of a casino, the job is likely to be ill-done. The
measure of success attained by Wall Street, regarded as an
institution of which the proper social purpose is to direct new
investment into the most profitable channels in terms of future
yield, cannot be claimed as one of the outstanding triumphs of laissez-faire
capitalismセwhich is not
surprising, if I am right in thinking that the best brains of
Wall Street have been in fact directed towards a different
object.
These tendencies are a scarcely avoidable outcome of our
having successfully organised 'liquid' investment markets. It is
usually agreed that casinos should, in the public interest, be
inaccessible and expensive. And perhaps the same is true of stock
exchanges. That the sins of the London Stock Exchange are less
than those of Wall Street may be due, not so much to differences
in national character, as to the fact that to the average
Englishman Throgmorton Street is, compared with Wall Street to
the average American, inaccessible and very expensive. The
jobber's 'turn', the high brokerage charges and the heavy transfer tax payable to the
Exchequer, which attend dealings on the London Stock Exchange,
sufficiently diminish the liquidity of the market (although the
practice of fortnightly accounts operates the other way) to rule
out a large proportion of the trinsaction characteristic of Wall
Street.
The introduction of a substantial government transfer tax on all
transactions might prove the most serviceable reform available,
with a view to mitigating the predominance of speculation over
enterprise in the United States.
The spectacle of modern investment markets has sometimes moved
me towards the conclusion that to make the purchase of an
investment permanent and indissoluble, like marriage, except by
reason of death or other grave cause, might be a useful remedy
for our contemporary evils. For this would force the investor to
direct his mind to the long-term prospects and to those only. But
a little consideration of this expedient brings us up against a
dilemma, and shows us how the liquidity of investment markets
often facilitates, though it sometimes impedes, the course of new
investment. For the fact that each individual investor flatters
himself that his commitment is 'liquid' (though this cannot be
true for all investors collectively) calms his nerves and makes
him much more willing to run a risk. If individual purchases of
investments were rendered illiquid, this might seriously impede
new investment, so long as alternative ways in which to
hold his savings are available to the individual. This is the
dilemma. So long as it is open to the individual to employ his
wealth in hoarding or lending money, the alternative of
purchasing actual capital assets cannot be rendered sufficiently
attractive (especially to the man who does not manage the capital assets and knows very little about
them), except by organising markets wherein these assets can be
easily realised for money.
The only radical cure for the crises of confidence which
afflict the economic life of the modern world would be to allow
the individual no choice between consuming his income and
ordering the production of the specific capital-asset which, even
though it be on precarious evidence, impresses him as the most
promising investment available to him. It might be that, at times
when he was more than usually assailed by doubts concerning the
future, he would turn in his perplexity towards more consumption
and less new investment. But that would avoid the disastrous,
cumulative and far-reaching repercussions of its being open to
him, when thus assailed by doubts, to spend his income neither on
the one nor on the other.
Those who have emphasised the social dangers of the hoarding
of money have, of course, had something similar to the above in
mind. But they have overlooked the possibility that the
phenomenon can occur without any change, or at least any
commensurate change, in the hoarding of money.
VII
Even apart from the instability due to speculation, there is
the instability due to the characteristic of human nature that a
large proportion of our positive activities depend on spontaneous
optimism rather than on a mathematical expectation, whether moral
or hedonistic or economic. Most, probably, of our decisions to do
something positive, the full consequences of which will be drawn
out over many days to come, can only be taken as a result of
animal spiritsセof a spontaneous urge
to action rather than inaction, and not as the outcome of a
weighted average of quantitative benefits multiplied by
quantitative probabilities. Enterprise only pretends to itself to be mainly actuated by the
statements in its own prospectus, however candid and sincere.
Only a little more than an expedition to the South Pole, is it
based on an exact calculation of benefits to come. Thus if the
animal spirits are dimmed and the spontaneous optimism falters,
leaving us to depend on nothing but a mathematical expectation,
enterprise will fade and die;セthough
fears of loss may have a basis no more reasonable than hopes of
profit had before.
It is safe to say that enterprise which depends on hopes
stretching into the future benefits the community as a whole. But
individual initiative will only be adequate when reasonable
calculation is supplemented and supported by animal spirits, so
that the thought of ultimate loss which often overtakes pioneers,
as experience undoubtedly tells us and them, is put aside as a
healthy man puts aside the expectation of death.
This means, unfortunately, not only that slumps and
depressions are exaggerated in degree, but that economic
prosperity is excessively dependent on a political and social
atmosphere which is congenial to the average business man. If the
fear of a Labour Government or a New Deal depresses enterprise,
this need not be the result either of a reasonable calculation or
of a plot with political intent;セit
is the mere consequence of upsetting the delicate balance of
spontaneous optimism. In estimating the prospects of investment,
we must have regard, therefore, to the nerves and hysteria and
even the digestions and reactions to the weather of those upon
whose spontaneous activity it largely depends.
We should not conclude from this that everything depends on
waves of irrational psychology. On the contrary, the state of
long-term expectation is often steady, and, even when it is not,
the other factors exert their compensating effects. We are merely
reminding ourselves that human decisions affecting the future,
whether personal or political or economic, cannot depend on strict mathematical expectation, since the basis for
making such calculations does not exist; and that it is our
innate urge to activity which makes the wheels go round, our
rational selves choosing between the alternatives as best we are
able, calculating where we can, but often falling back for our
motive on whim or sentiment or chance.
VIII
There are, moreover, certain important factors which somewhat
mitigate in practice the effects of our ignorance of the future.
Owing to the operation of compound interest combined with the
likelihood of obsolescence with the passage of time, there are
many individual investments of which the prospective yield is
legitimately dominated by the returns of the comparatively near
future. In the case of the most important class of very long-term
investments, namely buildings, the risk can be frequently
transferred from the investor to the occupier, or at least shared
between them, by means of long-term contracts, the risk being
outweighed in the mind of the occupier by the advantages of
continuity and security of tenure. In the case of another
important class of long-term investments, namely public
utilities, a substantial proportion of the prospective yield is
practically guaranteed by monopoly privileges coupled with the
right to charge such rates as will provide a certain stipulated
margin. Finally there is a growing class of investments entered
upon by, or at the risk of; public authorities, which are frankly
influenced in making the investment by a general presumption of
there being prospective social advantages from the investment,
whatever its commercial yield may prove to be within a wide
range, and without seeking to be satisfied that the mathematical
expectation of the yield is at least equal to the current rate of
interest,セthough the rate which the
public authority has to pay may still play a decisive part in
determining the scale of investment operations which it can
afford.
Thus after giving full weight to the importance of the
influence of short-period changes in the state of long-term
expectation as distinct from changes in the rate of interest, we
are still entitled to return to the latter as exercising, at any
rate, in normal circumstances, a great, though not a decisive,
influence on the rate of investment. Only experience, however,
can show how far management of the rate of interest is capable of
continuously stimulating the appropriate volume of investment.
For my own part I am now somewhat sceptical of the success of
a merely monetary policy directed towards influencing the rate of
interest. I expect to see the State, which is in a position to
calculate the marginal efficiency of capital-goods on long views
and on the basis of the general social advantage, taking an ever
greater responsibility for directly organising investment; since
it seems likely that the fluctuations in the market estimation of
the marginal efficiency of different types of capital, calculated
on the principles I have described above, will be too great to be
offset by any practicable changes in the rate of interest.